[This piece is a substantially-revised version of an earlier post, 'Ethics in a nutshell'.]
Meta-ethical questions are a bit like questions in the philosophy of mathematics, where various forms of platonism or realism do battle with more mundane interpretations. The key difference, I would suggest, is that the philosophy of mathematics has very little impact on the way mathematics is done, whereas meta-ethical disputes do impinge on normative (or prescriptive) ethics as practised by philosophers (though not, it must be said, on most ordinary ethical decision-making).
Unfortunately, meta-ethical disputes (which are often driven by deeply-felt convictions about the nature of human life and reality) are not readily resolvable, posing problems not only for meta-ethics but also for normative ethics.
Moral reasoning is complex and difficult enough, even if one is working – like many religious thinkers – within a generally accepted broader framework. But if there is no agreed-upon framework then conclusions are going to be – to say the least – very contestable.
And what of science? Science can, I believe, change the way we see the world in a way that philosophy can't. Though there is an important distinction to be maintained between the descriptive and the normative, between scientific and value-based judgements, science can undoubtedly offer new insights into value-based questions.
Our evolving understanding of the natural world and our place in it has a profound impact not only on how we see particular moral issues but also on how we frame and respond to general questions about human values, responsibility and freedom.
For example, 'ought' implies 'can', and the findings of science have a lot to say on what is realistically possible in terms of human behavior and what is not.
More generally, as our knowledge of human psychology has advanced, there have been – and there will continue to be – changes, both subtle and profound, in the way we think about right and wrong and conscience and guilt – and also changes to institutional mechanisms for dealing with anti-social and criminal behavior.
One approach to descriptive ethics which is not strictly scientific but which complements more rigorous approaches involves looking at how adjectives like 'ethical' and 'moral', auxiliaries like 'should' and nouns like 'obligation' or 'duty' are actually used in ordinary day-to-day contexts, and attempting to discern the implicit social rules and expectations which underlie the use of such expressions.
Every society, every social group, incorporates implicit rules of behavior. These rules (some relating to etiquette or manners, others to morality) can be studied and described like any other aspect of social life, though such descriptions will of necessity be incomplete and somewhat interpretive.
These systems of implicit moral rules coexist, of course, with explicit rules, as exemplified in systems of law and regulation. Though my focus here is on the former, it's important to be aware of the subtle, complex and often contentious relations between the two.
Just as the law is a system of enforceable explicit rules, so morality can be seen as a system of implicit rules. And just as the law outlines legal responsibilities and confers certain legal rights, so moral systems can be seen to assign responsibilities and confer certain moral rights. If you break society's explicit laws and are discovered, formal mechanisms of enforcement and justice are set in train. Similarly, if you break implicit moral rules, informal mechanisms (like disapproval and ostracism) will likely be triggered. The basic principle (hard-wired into our brains, perhaps) is that if you flout the rules you forfeit your right to the benefits and protections those rules might potentially provide.
Normative, as distinct from descriptive, approaches to ethics involve the individual actually becoming ethically engaged (rather than just describing what is). This will involve making or accepting or rejecting particular moral judgements or affirming or endorsing or arguing for particular judgements or values. It inevitably involves interpreting social rules, sometimes criticizing, and sometimes rejecting them.
Deontic logic traditionally divides behaviors into three broad classes: obligatory, impermissible and optional. ('Optional', by far the most appealing, is also, plausibly, by far the largest of the three classes.)
It's a complex branch of logic, but the real complications and challenges of practical moral thinking are not so much logical as contextual. Because, obviously, the general situation and the specific position(s) of the individual(s) involved need to be taken fully into account.
Times have changed since F.H. Bradley wrote his famous essay, 'My station and its duties' [a chapter, actually, of his book Ethical Studies (1876)], but the basic principle of the contextuality of ethics still applies. A person's duties or obligations derive in large part from (or at least cannot be assessed without taking into account) his or her positions in complex societal, professional and familial structures.
The key question in ethics is a situated-first-person question: what should I – in a particular situation at a particular time – do (or refrain from doing)? I say this is the key question in ethics, but such a question (and this is reflected in the ambiguity of the word 'should') often goes beyond ethics or morality, and merges with questions of prudence or etiquette or other areas or dimensions of life.
Unacceptable behavior causing serious harm to others, however, is clearly an issue in which ethical (and probably also legal) considerations will dominate.
What of ethical subjectivism? Is it a threat or a problem? My view is that, if normative ethics is seen as something theoretical, as an area of study to be compared and contrasted with descriptive (psychological or sociological) approaches, the former will inevitably suffer from the comparison, especially concerning claims to having an objective basis.
But if, on the other hand, normative ethics is seen in a more practical light, seen as an integral part of actually living and choosing rather than in purely academic or epistemic terms, then questions of objectivity versus subjectivity may not even arise.
The fact is, we are all forced to make ethical and other value-based decisions all the time. And, while empirical knowledge, reason and rational discourse can play an important part in these decisions, other more obscure elements are also inevitably in play.
This looks to me like the story of someone struggling their way out of a (meta-ethical) straightjacket.
ReplyDeleteWhen people theorise about morality they like to first convert it into a set or collection of rules. But it's not like that, I think. Do you judge others in terms of whether they have followed some rule or other? Do you yourself follow rules for your behaviour? I don't. In law and etiquette and of course games rules may be important but morality is different in that it can't be made rule-like.
Religious ethics may have bequeathed to us some "commandments", though I think they are always interpreted into a non-rule-like form. "Though shalt not kill" has to become a statement about murder, that is wrongful killing. There's no rule against wrongful killing. It's wrong already, so no rule is required to make it wrong.
I am relating implicit rules and expectations to descriptive ethics, and by rules I just mean (not precisely specifiable) patterns of social expectation.
DeleteBut ethical behavior/judgements involve(s) going beyond the rules – interpreting, criticizing, rejecting, etc. Even accepting some social norm or expectation involves going beyond it (choosing, in a sense, to conform). I make the point strongly in the last paragraph that ethical behavior is not just about rules.
I think I see your point about the meta-ethical straitjacket. It's just that I am trying to start from an objective, naturalistic, social science-like view of things, and then relate this to lived experience (in the light of what we are learning about the significance of unconscious brain processes).
On the other hand, you seem to be starting from the intuitions of lived experience and a position of moral realism. (As well as having (I think) rather more faith in the power of human reason than I do!)
I think the "debate" about moral realism and anti-realism is ill-formed from the start, so I'm not wishing to join in with it. It is the straitjacket! (correct spelling this time).
DeleteI would like to be as objective, naturalistic and social-science-like as anyone. I just don't see these as posing any great problem for morality. I read people who like you do see various problems, but I don't feel at all compelled by that view.
I have some doubts about that meta-ethical debate also, and have only reluctantly talked here and there about moral realism and anti-realism.
DeleteBut one distinction which is clearer, I think, is between a religious view of ethics (which goes beyond naturalism to posit a non-naturalistic basis for ethics and justice) and a rigorously secular view. It makes a difference, I think, because in the religious view there is no possibility of genuinely different and competing ethical systems; and, also, some may well be inclined to live differently – more in conformity to, say, Buddhist precepts – if they believed that the nature of their subsequent lives was being determined by their present actions and way of life.
I'm not saying there is a clear line between religious and other views of the world however. Stoicism and Platonism in their various forms and all sorts of other philosophical or more or less mystical traditions and outlooks complicate the picture.
Is there a problem with rigorously naturalistic ethics? Part of me (the better part) says no. Why should there be?
A part of me still wonders, however, whether perhaps Nietzsche and others like him weren't onto something.
But, as I indicated, my better half is an optimist – quite sensible, rational and even witty once or twice a year.
Great post thankyouu
ReplyDelete